Responses

Download PDFPDF
Always a burden? Healthcare providers’ perspectives on moral distress
Compose Response

Plain text

  • No HTML tags allowed.
  • Web page addresses and e-mail addresses turn into links automatically.
  • Lines and paragraphs break automatically.
Author Information
First or given name, e.g. 'Peter'.
Your last, or family, name, e.g. 'MacMoody'.
Your email address, e.g. higgs-boson@gmail.com
Your role and/or occupation, e.g. 'Orthopedic Surgeon'.
Your organization or institution (if applicable), e.g. 'Royal Free Hospital'.
Statement of Competing Interests

PLEASE NOTE:

  • A rapid response is a moderated but not peer reviewed online response to a published article in a BMJ journal; it will not receive a DOI and will not be indexed unless it is also republished as a Letter, Correspondence or as other content. Find out more about rapid responses.
  • We intend to post all responses which are approved by the Editor, within 14 days (BMJ Journals) or 24 hours (The BMJ), however timeframes cannot be guaranteed. Responses must comply with our requirements and should contribute substantially to the topic, but it is at our absolute discretion whether we publish a response, and we reserve the right to edit or remove responses before and after publication and also republish some or all in other BMJ publications, including third party local editions in other countries and languages
  • Our requirements are stated in our rapid response terms and conditions and must be read. These include ensuring that: i) you do not include any illustrative content including tables and graphs, ii) you do not include any information that includes specifics about any patients,iii) you do not include any original data, unless it has already been published in a peer reviewed journal and you have included a reference, iv) your response is lawful, not defamatory, original and accurate, v) you declare any competing interests, vi) you understand that your name and other personal details set out in our rapid response terms and conditions will be published with any responses we publish and vii) you understand that once a response is published, we may continue to publish your response and/or edit or remove it in the future.
  • By submitting this rapid response you are agreeing to our terms and conditions for rapid responses and understand that your personal data will be processed in accordance with those terms and our privacy notice.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.

Vertical Tabs

Other responses

Jump to comment:

  • Published on:
    the value of, and obstacles to, reflective practice
    • Sebastian Kraemer, health staff group consultant (retired paediatric psychiatrist) Tavistock & Portman NHS Trust

    Moral distress is a good 'umbrella' term but it tends to invite diversionary philosophising when in truth we all know that work in intensive care puts enormous emotional pressures on staff. These can be attended to but as the paper shows, cannot be eradicated. Health care is not a mechanical process. As one of the subjects in this study said "if we removed moral distress we would be like robots" (F443).

    In my response to an earlier paper on this theme by the same authors https://adc.bmj.com/content/101/8/701.responses I discussed the benefits and limitations of facilitated discussions. One of the most striking comments from a neonatal intensive care nurse in one such meeting was "if you don't talk about it you don't know it's bad" http://bit.ly/1OyKcfl which perfectly captures our essential ambivalence about looking at troubling experiences in any depth. We are after all practitioners, and the tradition of 'getting on with it' - with occasional intelligent and practical thoughts on process - is the prevailing culture in most health services. Yet after almost 40 years as a psychiatrist in paediatric settings I know that there is a hunger for less systematic, but no less disciplined, attention to the daily experience of health work. This short paper 'stop running and start thinking' (Kraemer 2019...

    Show More
    Conflict of Interest:
    None declared.
  • Published on:
    The value of accepting good with bad in moral distress: a response to Benjamin Hickox
    • Trisha M Prentice, Neonatologist The Royal Women's Hospital, Melbourne
    • Other Contributors:
      • Lynn Gillam, n/a
      • Peter G Davis, n/a
      • Annie Janvier, n/a

    We agree that conceptual clarity is of great value. Furthermore we acknowledge that some ‘distress’ experienced by our clinicians was not of a moral nature – such as the distress that results from tragic circumstances. We believe that in practice, distress and moral distress overlap. It can be difficult for clinicians to isolate the precise aetiology of their distress. We have furthermore acknowledged that these factors mean that the frequency of ‘moral distress’ may be overestimated in this study. However we are unclear why the ‘distress’ experienced by our clinicians is better labelled as ‘moral stress’. We maintain that conceptual clarity must be of clinical significance and be meaningful to those experiencing it. The clinicians participating were not uncomfortable with the idea that good things could arise from ‘distressing’ situations. It seems a disservice to the healthcare professionals in our study experiencing it to relabel it as ‘stress’ rather than ‘distress’ for the purpose of a less unsettling conclusion. We assume that Mr Hickox remains sceptical that moral distress, as strictly defined (that is, where a clinician feels anguish due to being constrained from acting in accordance with his/her moral judgement), may have some positive attributes. We will outline why we believe that in addition to decreasing moral distress and it’s negative consequences, we – and...

    Show More
    Conflict of Interest:
    None declared.
  • Published on:
    Moral distress is always a burden. Moral stress is not. The importance of a priori conceptual clarity.

    It is a deleterious proposition to declare benefits to moral distress. In their recent response, Epstein and Hurst (2017) eloquently articulated many reasons for this. A better approach may be to invoke the work of Hans Selye (1974) and the parallels drawn by Rambur, Vallett, Cohen, and Tarule (2010) in advocating for the potential benefits of moral stress; not moral distress. The authors of the present article effectively revealed clinicians' general misunderstanding and misapplication of the concept of moral distress. Indeed, the authors acknowledged this explicitly: "This study demonstrates the importance of asking what clinical providers mean by 'moral distress' and/or what researchers mean when investigating this phenomenon" (p. F4). The authors' conclusions about frequency of moral distress and "inevitability" of moral distress are based on clinician self-report; not on a generally accepted definition of moral distress. Likewise, the authors do not use a validated, reliable tool to quantify moral distress (such as the Moral Distress Thermometer, Wocial & Weaver, 2013). Much qualitative research has been done that has clarified the concept of moral distress; it is not simply whatever the clinician says it is. As ethicist Denise Dudzinski (2016) stated, "clinicians benefit by distinguishing between distress and moral distress" and "without mapping the ethical dimensions of distress, clinicians are left...

    Show More
    Conflict of Interest:
    None declared.